ABSTRACT

Implicit in all the chapters of this book, as in the general run of historical

writing, is the conviction that it is possible to make valid statements about

what happened in the past. Here, for example, one chapter has told the story of

Sir Thomas Seymour’s last years, another has offered an explanation for the

fall of Anne Boleyn, and another has explored the role of the nobility in Tudor

England. Often the interpretations offered by other historians have been

carefully scrutinised and modified or rejected. Underlying such often detailed

papers is the belief that some interpretations are nearer the truth – because

more solidly grounded in the evidence and because more rigorously argued –

than others. On the whole such convictions are much more commonly left

unarticulated by working historians than boldly defended: they seem so

obvious as not to need explanation. Yet in recent years they have come under

attack, as the quotations with which this chapter begins show, and it is that

challenge that has prompted the response that follows. It was first conceived as

a lecture in a first-year course on Approaches to History, and it is intended

above all to draw the attention of fledgling students of history to what seems to

me a mistaken and harmful approach to history, and warn them against it. This

approach will here for the sake of convenience (and in full awareness of the

risks of simplification) be labelled ‘postmodernism’. The origins of ‘post-

modernism’ lie not in the work of historians, but rather in other disciplines,

particularly philosophy, especially the ideas of Nietzsche and Heidegger,

linguistics, especially Saussure, and literary theory, especially Barthes and

Derrida. Their ideas have become very fashionable in departments of literature

and cultural studies, especially in the new universities. They have been taken up

by those who see themselves, in the words of the journal they have established,

as Rethinking History. Most of the examples given above are taken from those

who are not so much historians as would-be philosophers of history who seek

to tell practising historians what is wrong with their practice. A few – but so

far not many – historians have in recent years been influenced by such ideas;

and, at a different level, what is best called a naive nihilism or relativism

characterises the assumptions of many students. It may thus be timely for one

historian deeply suspicious of ‘postmodernism’ to set out reasons for such

suspicion.