ABSTRACT

It is a necessary condition for political representation ‘that the actions of . . .

policy makers are supposed to be responsive to the wishes of the people’

(Powell 2004, p. 273). For representation to be democratic, responsiveness

must be accompanied by ‘institutionalized arrangements that reliably create

such connections’, most importantly and irreplaceably ‘the free and competitive

national election in which all citizens can participate equally’ (pp. 273-274).

Democratic parliaments are assemblies of winners of such competitive elections.

In their classic study of substantive representation in the US Congress, Miller and

Stokes (1963) identified two mechanisms to ensure the representatives’ respon-

siveness: (a) the electoral process itself, which gives constituents the possibility

to choose representatives who pledge policies in line with their own preferences;

and (b) between elections, the representatives’ actions in the legislature are con-

nected with constituents through the former’s perceptions of the preferences of

the latter (anticipating voter responses in the next election). Assuming that

members of Parliament (MPs) care about getting re-elected and voters care

about MPs’ responsiveness, MPs have incentives to communicate their policy

proposals and explain their legislative activities to voters; voters have incentives

to communicate their policy preferences to candidates. While Miller and Stokes

(1963) modelled constituent-deputy relations as a dyadic process of

representation between voters and representatives, European party democracies

require some theoretical and empirical adjustments to account for the role of pol-

itical parties as well.