ABSTRACT

Throughout legal history, enthusiasm for unjust enrichment has tended to come in waves. The

same pattern has occurred several times. The idea is picked up and popularised; the more

analytically-minded step in to make it precise; briefly it is fashionable; and then, as the implications

of the analysis sink in, it falls from favour into a marsh of technicality. The transient dawn of

Dawson’s survey of ‘unjust enrichment’, composed in the 1950s, identified three major

outbreaks of the notion in the history of the West. We are now living through a fourth, on much the

same pattern. There was the initial wild enthusiasm in the 1960s and 1970s, as ‘unjust enrichment’

seemed to its supporters to provide the explanation for a wide range of doctrines. Then in the 1980s

the analytical lawyers stepped in, squeezing the slippery notion of unjust enrichment into a fairly

precise mould, the famous or infamous ‘taxonomic model’ of the subject. Inevitably, the decline

began in the 1990s, and still continues. Dawson’s moral is still true: once you remove the flexibility of

‘unjust enrichment’, you also remove the main emotional and moral reasons for supporting it. For the

last decade, the subject has become more and more technical; the theory once thought to explain so

much is acknowledged to explain less and less. The impenetrability of the debate to outsiders is a

commonplace of the conference circuit. And even those academics who devote themselves to the

subject full time complain about how hard it is to keep up with all the new writing. There is more and

Living through this rising tide of incomprehensibility, it is vital to remember essentials. The

taxonomic model of unjust enrichment is supposed to be a set of concepts explaining and

rationalising certain areas of that law. If it fails to do that, then it has no place in the law. If most

of the intellectual effort in the area goes into a-not conspicuously successful-attempt to reconcile

the theory with judicial holdings, then it is time to call it a day. If, by contrast, the taxonomic

approach gives great insights into the law, that would be a reason not only for retaining it, but for

extending its use. And if the increasingly complicated academic theory represents a deeper and

more sophisticated knowledge of the law, then undoubtedly this is a gain. The question is: which

are we dealing with here?