ABSTRACT

Euclidean space . . . is literally flattened out, confined to a surface . . . The person who

sees and knows only how to see, the person who draws and knows only how to put

marks on a sheet of paper, the person who drives around and knows only how to drive

a car – all contribute in their way to the mutilation of a space which is everywhere sliced

up . . . the driver is concerned only with steering himself to his destination and in looking

about sees only what he needs to see for that purpose; he thus perceives only his route,

which has been materialised, mechanised and technicised and he sees it from one angle

only – that of its functionality: speed, readability, facility . . . The reading of space that

has been manufactured with readability in mind amounts to a sort of pleonasm, that of

a ‘pure’ and illusory transparency. Space is defined in this context in terms of the

perception of an abstract subject, such as the driver of a motor vehicle, equipped with a

collective common sense, namely the capacity to read the symbols of the highway code,

and with a sole organ – the eye – placed in the service of his movement within the visual

field. Thus, space appears solely in its reduced forms. Volume leaves the field to surface

and any overall view surrenders to visual signals spaced out along fixed trajectories already

laid down in the ‘plan’. An extraordinary – indeed unthinkable, impossible – confusion

gradually arises between space and surface, with the latter determining a spatial

abstraction which it endows with a half-imaginary, half-real physical existence. This

abstract space eventually becomes the simulacrum of a full space . . . Travelling – walking

or strolling about – becomes an actually experienced, gestural simulation of the formerly

urban activity of encounter, of movement amongst concrete existences.1