ABSTRACT

The public interest1 in a narrower definition of the concept and nature of

political religions is definitely due to the totalitarian movements that have so emphatically marked the face of the twentieth century. The political

religions of pre-modern societies, by contrast, seem to have been securely

archived in the respective specialist disciplines. Under these circumstances,

the question as to the totalitarian implications of the sun-cult of Akhenaton

or the Geneva theocracy of Calvin might scarcely mobilise the combat

battalions of political correctness; they are more likely to be treated

controversially in the responsible specialist organs. That these pre-modern

societies formed theocracies that – en miniature – underwent every variation of wars of faith conceivable might belong among the pieces of knowledge

that arouse no further notice. Scientific concern with the political religions

of totalitarian movements of the modern era, by contrast, cannot work

undisturbed in an encapsulated space of the archives of specialist

disciplines; instead, it must always expect a public that reacts to scientific

problems and results with praise or censure, critique or agreement, outrage

or judgement. The explosiveness of the scientific study of the modern tota-

litarian movements and their political religions rests not so much with the data submitted and their incorporation into comprehensive theories; it is

based, rather, upon a matter that is seldom openly confessed and extends

far beyond the limits of the cultural sciences. What is involved is the problem

of the religious justification and motivation of the monstrous crimes that

these totalitarian movements practised with the help of institutions and

technologies of the utmost modernity. Moral judgements, allocations of

guilt and exonerations for those who commit religiously motivated and

legitimated crimes are indivisibly tied to the researching of problems in this area. In this context, both condemnations and exonerations are bound up

with one’s position;2 they are, therefore, dependent upon value judgements

and the foundations of faith that underpin them. Representatives of a uni-

versalism of human rights also judge in terms of their own position: in

terms, namely, of their faith-conviction that there are transculturally valid

standards of value that must obtain universally. It is necessary, therefore, to

answer the question as to whether the monstrous crimes that were planned

and executed by these totalitarian movements under explicit invocation of

their ideological postulate of destruction were in fact brought about and driven on by religious basic motives. Or was it only perversions of religious

faith that were involved? If this were the case, then such perversions would

have to be regarded as illusory legitimations and be eliminated from reli-

gious legitimation in the more narrow sense. Are the roots of the barbarian

inhumanity of modern totalitarian movements in fact religious, then? Did

the movements legitimate this inhumanity as a necessary deed in terms of

salvation history? Is there a religion of inhumanity, under the conditions of

modernity, which provides the technical means and prerequisites by which to let the crimes of the totalitarian movements penetrate into areas that

were hitherto inconceivable in the history of inhumanity? Stated differently:

would the crimes of the totalitarian movements also have been carried out if

those movements had not had at their disposal inner-worldly doctrines of

salvation that conveyed their adherents the certainty of belief that their

crimes were necessary and legitimate?