Skip to main content
Taylor & Francis Group Logo
    Advanced Search

    Click here to search products using title name,author name and keywords.

    • Login
    • Hi, User  
      • Your Account
      • Logout
      Advanced Search

      Click here to search products using title name,author name and keywords.

      Breadcrumbs Section. Click here to navigate to respective pages.

      Chapter

      FEMINIST CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM
      loading

      Chapter

      FEMINIST CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM

      DOI link for FEMINIST CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM

      FEMINIST CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM book

      FEMINIST CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM

      DOI link for FEMINIST CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM

      FEMINIST CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM book

      ByElizabeth Potter
      BookFeminism and Philosophy of Science

      Click here to navigate to parent product.

      Edition 1st Edition
      First Published 2006
      Imprint Routledge
      Pages 34
      eBook ISBN 9780203646663
      Share
      Share

      ABSTRACT

      Helen Longino understands a good epistemology as both setting outthe conditions that must be satisfied in order for people to ascribe the status “knowledge” to something and describing what people do. A good philosophy of science, then, describes the work of scientists and gives a detailed theory of the conditions that must be satisfied in order for the scientific community to know something rather than hypothesize it (Longino 2002: 10). The claim that philosophers should describe what people do, e.g. their knowledge-producing practices, is contested by philosophers for many reasons: many wish to maintain a strong distinction between philosophy as “conceptual” and social or natural science as “empirical,” and/or maintain a sharp distinction between facts and values, and/or believe that descriptive epistemology and philosophy of science leads to pernicious relativism. But Longino belongs to the school of epistemologists and philosophers of science who wish to naturalize epistemology and philosophy of science inasmuch as she believes that philosophy must give accounts of knowledge in general and scientific knowledge in particular that are based more closely on what scientists (or other knowers) actually do when they produce and transmit knowledge. But Longino does not belong with those naturalizers who think that philosophy should no longer concern itself with norms (i.e. the conditions that must be satisfied in order for people to ascribe the status “knowledge” to something) and should not produce normative accounts of knowledge. Philosophy should be both normative and empirical.This is why she sets up The Fate of Knowledge as breaking down the dichotomy between social and rational accounts of knowledge (Longino 2002: 10).

      T&F logoTaylor & Francis Group logo
      • Policies
        • Privacy Policy
        • Terms & Conditions
        • Cookie Policy
        • Privacy Policy
        • Terms & Conditions
        • Cookie Policy
      • Journals
        • Taylor & Francis Online
        • CogentOA
        • Taylor & Francis Online
        • CogentOA
      • Corporate
        • Taylor & Francis Group
        • Taylor & Francis Group
        • Taylor & Francis Group
        • Taylor & Francis Group
      • Help & Contact
        • Students/Researchers
        • Librarians/Institutions
        • Students/Researchers
        • Librarians/Institutions
      • Connect with us

      Connect with us

      Registered in England & Wales No. 3099067
      5 Howick Place | London | SW1P 1WG © 2022 Informa UK Limited